>> his
> answer is no better. We need an "integral" model based on the
> classical
> view, in a form that recognizes and incorporates the points raised by
> other
> perspectives.
>
>
>
> Lakoff says (below)
>
>
>
> In summary, reason is not, in any way, a transcendent feature of the
> universe or of disembodied mind. Instead, it is shaped crucially by
> the
> peculiarities of our human bodies, by the remarkable details of the
> neural
> structure of our brains, and by the specifics of our everyday
> functioning in
> the world.
>
>
>
> Does "2 +2 = 4" have its roots in neurology and "embodied mind -- or
> is that
> logic "independent of the flesh"?
>
>
>
> Some people on this list have roots that extend way back into the
> historical
> beginnings of computer science -- so maybe this argument, which for me
> is
> still very much alive, might prompt some comments.
>
>
>
> Thanks
>
>
>
>
>
> ***************************
>
>
>
> Here's an excerpt from Chapter 1 of a more recent book that shows the
> direction his thought has gone.
>
>
>
>
http://www.nytimes.com/books/first/l/lakoff-philosophy.html
>
>
>
> Philosophy in the Flesh
>
> The Embodied Mind and its Challenge to Western Thought
>
>
>
>
>
> How Cognitive Science Reopens
>
> Central Philosophical Questions
>
>
>
> The mind is inherently embodied.
>
>
>
> Thought is mostly unconscious.
>
>
>
> Abstract concepts are largely metaphorical.
>
>
>
> These are three major findings of cognitive science. More than two
> millennia
> of a priori philosophical speculation about these aspects of reason
> are
> over. Because of these discoveries, philosophy can never be the same
> again.
>
>
>
> When taken together and considered in detail, these three findings
> from the
> science of the mind are inconsistent with central parts of Western
> philosophy. They require a thorough rethinking of the most popular
> current
> approaches, namely, Anglo-American analytic philosophy and
> postmodernist
> philosophy.
>
>
>
> This book asks: What would happen if we started with these empirical
> discoveries about the nature of mind and constructed philosophy anew?
> The
> answer is that an empirically responsible philosophy would require our
> culture to abandon some of its deepest philosophical assumptions. This
> book
> is an extensive study of what many of those changes would be in
> detail.
>
>
>
> Our understanding of what the mind is matters deeply. Our most basic
> philosophical beliefs are tied inextricably to our view of reason.
> Reason
> has been taken for over two millennia as the defining characteristic
> of
> human beings. Reason includes not only our capacity for logical
> inference,
> but also our ability to conduct inquiry, to solve problems, to
> evaluate, to
> criticize, to deliberate about how we should act, and to reach an
> understanding of ourselves, other people, and the world. A radical
> change in
> our understanding of reason is therefore a radical change in our
> understanding of ourselves. It is surprising to discover, on the basis
> of
> empirical research, that human rationality is not at all what the
> Western
> philosophical tradition has held it to be. But it is shocking to
> discover
> that we are very different from what our philosophical tradition has
> told us
> we are.
>
>
>
> Let us start with the changes in our understanding of reason:
>
>
>
>
>
> * Reason is not disembodied, as the tradition has largely held, but
> arises
> from the nature of our brains, bodies, and bodily experience. This is
> not
> just the innocuous and obvious claim that we need a body to reason;
> rather,
> it is the striking claim that the very structure of reason itself
> comes from
> the details of our embodiment. The same neural and cognitive
> mechanisms that
> allow us to perceive and move around also create our conceptual
> systems and
> modes of reason. Thus, to understand reason we must understand the
> details
> of our visual system, our motor system, and the general mechanisms of
> neural
> binding. In summary, reason is not, in any way, a transcendent feature
> of
> the universe or of disembodied mind. Instead, it is shaped crucially
> by the
> peculiarities of our human bodies, by the remarkable details of the
> neural
> structure of our brains, and by the specifics of our everyday
> functioning in
> the world.
>
> * Reason is evolutionary, in that abstract reason builds on and makes
> use of
> forms of perceptual and motor inference present in "lower" animals.
> The
> result is a Darwinism of reason, a rational Darwinism: Reason, even in
> its
> most abstract form, makes use of, rather than transcends, our animal
> nature.
> The discovery that reason is evolutionary utterly changes our relation
> to
> other animals and changes our conception of human beings as uniquely
> rational. Reason is thus not an essence that separates us from other
> animals; rather, it places us on a continuum with them.
>
> * Reason is not "universal" in the transcendent sense; that is, it is
> not
> part of the structure of the universe. It is universal, however, in
> that it
> is a capacity shared universally by all human beings. What allows it
> to be
> shared are the commonalities that exist in the way our minds are
> embodied.
>
> * Reason is not completely conscious, but mostly unconscious.
>
> * Reason is not purely literal, but largely metaphorical and
> imaginative.
>
> * Reason is not dispassionate, but emotionally engaged.
>
>
>
> This shift in our understanding of reason is of vast proportions, and
> it
> entails a corresponding shift in our understanding of what we are as
> human
> beings. What we now know about the mind is radically at odds with the
> major
> classical philosophical views of what a person is.
>
>
>
> For example, there is no Cartesian dualistic person, with a mind
> separate
> from and independent of the body, sharing exactly the same disembodied
> transcendent reason with everyone else, and capable of knowing
> everything
> about his or her mind simply by self-reflection. Rather, the mind is
> inherently embodied, reason is shaped by the body, and since most
> thought is
> unconscious, the mind cannot be known simply by self-reflection.
> Empirical
> study is necessary.
>
>
>
> There exists no Kantian radically autonomous person, with absolute
> freedom
> and a transcendent reason that correctly dictates what is and isn't
> moral.
> Reason, arising from the body, doesn't transcend the body. What
> universal
> aspects of reason there are arise from the commonalities of our bodies
> and
> brains and the environments we inhabit. The existence of these
> universals
> does not imply that reason transcends the body. Moreover, since
> conceptual
> systems vary significantly, reason is not entirely universal.
>
>
>
> Since reason is shaped by the body, it is not radically free, because
> the
> possible human conceptual systems and the possible forms of reason are
> limited. In addition, once we have learned a conceptual system, it is
> neurally instantiated in our brains and we are not free to think just
> anything. Hence, we have no absolute freedom in Kant's sense, no full
> autonomy. There is no a priori, purely philosophical basis for a
> universal
> concept of morality and no transcendent, universal pure reason that
> could
> give rise to universal moral laws.
>
>
>
> The utilitarian person, for whom rationality is economic
> rationality--the
> maximization of utility--does not exist. Real human beings are not,
> for the
> most part, in conscious control of--or even consciously aware
> of--their
> reasoning. Most of their reason, besides, is based on various kinds of
> prototypes, framings, and metaphors. People seldom engage in a form of
> economic reason that could maximize utility.
>
>
>
> The phenomenological person, who through phenomenological
> introspection
> alone can discover everything there is to know about the mind and the
> nature
> of experience, is a fiction. Although we can have a theory of a vast,
> rapidly and automatically operating cognitive unconscious, we have no
> direct
> conscious access to its operation and therefore to most of our
> thought.
> Phenomenological reflection, though valuable in revealing the
> structure of
> experience, must be supplemented by empirical research into the
> cognitive
> unconscious.
>
>
>
> There is no poststructuralist person--no completely decentered subject
> for
> whom all meaning is arbitrary, totally relative, and purely
> historically
> contingent, unconstrained by body and brain. The mind is not merely
> embodied, but embodied in such a way that our conceptual systems draw
> largely upon the commonalities of our bodies and of the environments
> we live
> in. The result is that much of a person's conceptual system is either
> universal or widespread across languages and cultures. Our conceptual
> systems are not totally relative and not merely a matter of historical
> contingency, even though a degree of conceptual relativity does exist
> and
> even though historical contingency does matter a great deal. The
> grounding
> of our conceptual systems in shared embodiment and bodily experience
> creates
> a largely centered self, but not a monolithic self.
>
>
>
> There exists no Fregean person--as posed by analytic philosophy--for
> whom
> thought has been extruded from the body. That is, there is no real
> person
> whose embodiment plays no role in meaning, whose meaning is purely
> objective
> and defined by the external world, and whose language can fit the
> external
> world with no significant role played by mind, brain, or body. Because
> our
> conceptual systems grow out of our bodies, meaning is grounded in and
> through our bodies. Because a vast range of our concepts are
> metaphorical,
> meaning is not entirely literal and the classical correspondence
> theory of
> truth is false. The correspondence theory holds that statements are
> true or
> false objectively, depending on how they map directly onto the
> world--independent of any human understanding of either the statement
> or the
> world. On the contrary, truth is mediated by embodied understanding
> and
> imagination. That does not mean that truth is purely subjective or
> that
> there is no stable truth. Rather, our common embodiment allows for
> common,
> stable truths.
>
>
>
> There is no such thing as a computational person, whose mind is like
> computer software, able to work on any suitable computer or neural
> hardware--whose mind somehow derives meaning from taking meaningless
> symbols
> as input, manipulating them by rule, and giving meaningless symbols as
> output. Real people have embodied minds whose conceptual systems arise
> from,
> are shaped by, and are given meaning through living human bodies. The
> neural
> structures of our brains produce conceptual systems and linguistic
> structures that cannot be adequately accounted for by formal systems
> that
> only manipulate symbols.
>
>
>
> Finally, there is no Chomskyan person, for whom language is pure
> syntax,
> pure form insulated from and independent of all meaning, context,
> perception, emotion, memory, attention, action, and the dynamic nature
> of
> communication. Moreover, human language is not a totally genetic
> innovation.
> Rather, central aspects of language arise evolutionarily from sensory,
> motor, and other neural systems that are present in "lower" animals.
>
>
>
> Classical philosophical conceptions of the person have stirred our
> imaginations and taught us a great deal. But once we understand the
> importance of the cognitive unconscious, the embodiment of mind, and
> metaphorical thought, we can never go back to a priori philosophizing
> about
> mind and language or to philosophical ideas of what a person is that
> are
> inconsistent with what we are learning about the mind.
>
>
>
> Given our new understanding of the mind, the question of what a human
> being
> is arises for us anew in the most urgent way.
>
>
>
>
>
>
>
>
>
> Bruce Schuman
>
>
(805) 966-9515, PO Box 23346, Santa Barbara CA 93101
>
>
>
> -----Original Message-----
> From:
ontolog-forum-bounces@xxxxxxxxxxxxxxxx
> [mailto:
ontolog-forum-bounces@xxxxxxxxxxxxxxxx] On Behalf Of John F
> Sowa
> Sent: Tuesday, July 15, 2014 3:26 PM
> To:
ontolog-forum@xxxxxxxxxxxxxxxx
> Subject: Re: [ontolog-forum] Paraconsistent Logic
>
>
>
> On 7/15/2014 6:02 PM, Philip Jackson wrote:
>
>> Googling "paraconsistent logic applications" returns 69,300 results
>> --
>
>> the first is a book titled "Paraconsistency: Logic and Applications".
>
>
>
> Thanks for the reference. It confirms my suspicions.
>
>
>
> The articles in that book are written by logicians and philosophers.
>
> What they call "applications" are not the kind that make a profit for
> investors.
>
>
>
> I'm sympathetic to those ideas. But it's important to distinguish
> applications that depend on grants from applications that people will
> pay
> money to use.
>
>
>
> John
>
> _________________________________________________________________
>
> Message Archives: <
http://ontolog.cim3.net/forum/ontolog-forum/>
>
http://ontolog.cim3.net/forum/ontolog-forum/
>
> Config Subscr:
> <
http://ontolog.cim3.net/mailman/listinfo/ontolog-forum/>
>
http://ontolog.cim3.net/mailman/listinfo/ontolog-forum/
>
> Unsubscribe: <mailto:
ontolog-forum-leave@xxxxxxxxxxxxxxxx>
> mailto:
ontolog-forum-leave@xxxxxxxxxxxxxxxx
>
> Shared Files: <
http://ontolog.cim3.net/file/>
>
http://ontolog.cim3.net/file/
> Community Wiki: <
http://ontolog.cim3.net/wiki/>
>
http://ontolog.cim3.net/wiki/ To join:
> <
http://ontolog.cim3.net/cgi-bin/wiki.pl?WikiHomePage#nid1J>
>