ontolog-forum
[Top] [All Lists]

Re: [ontolog-forum] Nonmonotonic Reasoning

To: "[ontolog-forum]" <ontolog-forum@xxxxxxxxxxxxxxxx>
From: Adrian Walker <adriandwalker@xxxxxxxxx>
Date: Fri, 23 Mar 2012 13:19:23 -0400
Message-id: <CABbsESdaY8QgeT+bM-Dr8Ft7Wsdutm8_K+_Y3FjRMHt7=Z6JRw@xxxxxxxxxxxxxx>
Hi John,

Nice summary of the issues.

It seems that 1. takes us outside first order logic into second order.  What are the computational complexity consequences?  Moving from P to NP perhaps?

                          Cheers,  -- Adrian

Internet Business Logic
A Wiki and SOA Endpoint for Executable Open Vocabulary English Q/A over SQL and RDF
Online at www.reengineeringllc.com   
Shared use is free, and there are no advertisements

Adrian Walker
Reengineering

 
On Fri, Mar 23, 2012 at 11:59 AM, John F. Sowa <sowa@xxxxxxxxxxx> wrote:
The topic of nonmonotonic reasoning has come up in many threads on
this list.  I'd like to make a few comments about it and cite some
references.

First, the term 'nonmonotonic reasoning' is broader than the term
'nonmonotonic logic'.  It includes methods of belief revision (or
theory revision).  Those methods keep the usual classical logic,
but they revise a classical theory by adding or deleting axioms
to create a new classical theory.

Second, the semantics of every version of nonmonotonic reasoning is
based on the semantics of a related classical logic.  For example,
query languages like SQL and rule-based languages like Prolog use
a nonmonotonic logic called *negation as failure* (NAF).  Proofs
in NAF systems can be defined in several ways:

 1. As nonmonotonic logic, add a new rule of inference to the rules
    for the corresponding classical logic:  if an attempted proof
    of a statement p fails, assume that p is false.

 2. As belief revision, use the Closed World Assumption (CWA) to
    revise the theory (axioms + facts) by adding the negation of
    every statement that uses the same ontology, but is not provable.
    Then you can use the classical rules of inference, but with a
    much larger set of axioms.

 3. Method #2 makes a huge revision to the axioms in one step.
    But it's possible to achieve the same effect by incrementally
    adding axioms one at a time as needed:  whenever a NAF step is
    used in a proof, add the new negated assumption to the set of
    axioms for the current theory.  As a result, the same proof can
    be carried out from the enlarged set of axioms, but with just
    classical inference rules.

Method #3 is an incremental method of belief revision that can use
exactly the same inference engine as the corresponding nonmonotonic
logic.  The only difference is that it saves each negated statement
and adds it to the list of axioms.  It shows that the difference
between nonmonotonic logic and belief revision can just be considered
a difference in terminology (at least for NAF logics).

For a general discussion of these issues, see the following book
on belief revision, which emphasizes the relationships among
nonmonotonic logics, classical logics, and belief revision:

   Makinson, David (2005) Bridges from Classical to Nomonotonic Logic,
   King's College Publications, London.

Makinson also happens to be the M in the AGM axioms for belief
revision.  The following review of his book summarizes some of
the issues:

   http://www.maths.manchester.ac.uk/~hykel/work/bridges-review/

See the end of this note for a few excerpts from the review.

For related information, see the first page of Makinson's own
web site, which has comments about his other articles:

   http://sites.google.com/site/davidcmakinson/

For a good review article with 110 references to the literature
on belief revision, see

   Peppas, Pavlos (2008) Belief revision, in F. van Harmelen,
   V. Lifschitz, & B. Porter, Handbook of Knowledge Representation,
   Elsevier, Amsterdam, pp. 317-359.

Note the last paragraph in the following excerpts from the review
of Makinson's book.  The cases for which the "unwelcome assumption"
can be avoided can be found by walking through the lattice of all
possible theories that can be stated in the given classical logic.

John
_____________________________________________________________________

Source: http://www.maths.manchester.ac.uk/~hykel/work/bridges-review/

The book [develops] the logico-mathematical apparatus required to
construct nonmonotonic inference operations out of the classical,
monotonic one...

Its key message is that nonmonotonic logics, as in fact many other
so-called non-standard logics, are not to be taken as alternatives to
the classical one, in the way, that is, in which intuitionistic logic is
regarded as opposed to classical logic. Both at the object- and at the
meta- level the importance of classical logic is beyond dispute in
nonmonotonic logics. Engaging in nonmonotonic logics means aiming at
extending classical logic, rather than replacing it tout court...

Chapters 2-4 constitute the core of the book in which the author
presents three canonical constructions to obtain nonmonotonic
consequence relations out of monotonic ones. The author follows a
general pattern for introducing such constructions. The starting point
is always the mathematical machinery provided by classical consequence.
It is fundamental to notice that the nonmonotonic consequence relations
discussed in the book all rest on the very same language as classical
propositional logic. The second step consists in introducing a bridge
consequence relation. Such a (monotonic) bridge is then used to
construct a nonmonotonic consequence relation...

The main idea of Chapter 2 - Using additional background assumptions -
is simple and powerful: distinguishing among local and background
assumptions. It is reasonable to believe that when making inferences we,
intelligent reasoners, do not consider all the information available to
us, that is the premisses of our logical argument, as "equally
conspicuous". In particular it seems appropriate to distinguish between
the information embodying "the current premises" of our argument - the
set of local assumptions - from the set of assumptions which we commit
to somehow tacitly - the set of background assumptions (or expectations)...

Allowing the set of background assumptions to vary - essentially in a
consistency preserving way - with the set of local assumption amounts to
enabling nonmonotonic reasoning, as captured by the default assumption
consequence relation, fully investigated in Section 2.2...

However, when considering default assumption consequence we face, in the
author's terminology, a basic Dilemma. Makinson proves, in fact, that if
the set of background assumptions is not closed under classical
consequence, then it is not language invariant...

As to the latter unwelcome consequence, a number of solutions are
discussed... All these variations allow the set of background
assumptions to be closed under classical consequence yet avoiding the
collapse of default assumption consequence into the classical one.
Section 2.3 (and the corresponding exercises and problems) illustrates
this at length...

_________________________________________________________________
Message Archives: http://ontolog.cim3.net/forum/ontolog-forum/
Config Subscr: http://ontolog.cim3.net/mailman/listinfo/ontolog-forum/
Unsubscribe: mailto:ontolog-forum-leave@xxxxxxxxxxxxxxxx
Shared Files: http://ontolog.cim3.net/file/
Community Wiki: http://ontolog.cim3.net/wiki/
To join: http://ontolog.cim3.net/cgi-bin/wiki.pl?WikiHomePage#nid1J



_________________________________________________________________
Message Archives: http://ontolog.cim3.net/forum/ontolog-forum/  
Config Subscr: http://ontolog.cim3.net/mailman/listinfo/ontolog-forum/  
Unsubscribe: mailto:ontolog-forum-leave@xxxxxxxxxxxxxxxx
Shared Files: http://ontolog.cim3.net/file/
Community Wiki: http://ontolog.cim3.net/wiki/ 
To join: http://ontolog.cim3.net/cgi-bin/wiki.pl?WikiHomePage#nid1J    (01)

<Prev in Thread] Current Thread [Next in Thread>