Thanks John for replies and the detailed review,
At first glance I would have though that you and Pieters share the same front, I wouldnt have thought that there could be so many 'differences' in your viewpoints
I am sure that If Pieter rebutted the discussion could end up being rather long ( surely interesting for some and maybe alienating for others)
Somehow I am relieved that you think the square is enough - but will try to understand the theory behind the dodecadron, I find it fascinating shape
(entirely trivial motive) and obviously it must be trying to say something
Currently I am interested in Logic in relation to information/knowledge systems design, for this purpose I am interested in finding work
that supports the arguments that discourse may be lacking
(Offlist apparently there is another world of untold opinions of people who obviously have become aware that free speech can, and will, indeed be used against them, so they stay well away from it)
I am interested in understadning what additional knowledge perspective we need to acquire to improve the usefulness of our information systems whatever shape it comes in
P
On Sat, Oct 17, 2009 at 8:20 PM, John F. Sowa <sowa@xxxxxxxxxxx> wrote:
Paola,
PDM> I would be interested in seeing you and Pieter argue over
> the contended points in a public discourse arena, and I am
> hopeful that you could come to some brief conclusion
A public debate might be exciting, but it's not necessary.
I suggest that anyone interested in the subject should take
a hard look at Seuren's assumptions:
Starting on page 1, he makes some points that are not controversial,
but he adds assumptions that make them dubious. Since I won't comment
on all of Seuren's assumptions, the numbering below is his:
1. "Progress in science is contingent upon taking the data seriously."
But he follows that with extremely controversial statements:
"In the cognitive sciences, the data is experiential intuitions.
In the semantics of natural language, data consists of semantic
experiential intuitions, including logical intuitions."
Intuitions aren't data. They are essential for hypotheses, but
every hypothesis must be tested with publicly observable data.
2. "The primary function of any signaling system, including natural
languages, is for the sign-giver (speaker) to enter a social
commitment with regard to the truth of a proposition."
Social commitment is essential for language, but the assumption
that propositions and truth are primary is not supported by the
data of language use. For infants learning language and for
adults who have a minimal use of a foreign language, requests
and questions are primary. Stating propositions is secondary.
4. "The relation between logic and language has been unclear from
the very beginning and all accepted logical systems violate
natural intuitions to some degree."
The first clause is certainly true. But the second clause
contains the dubious term "natural intuitions", which Seuren
identifies with his own hypotheses.
5. "To understand the semantics of natural language it is necessary
to investigate the possibility of reconstructing NATURAL HUMAN
LOGIC."
He assumes that there exists a fixed propositional system that
supports NL semantics. But there are many more reasonable
assumptions. Terrence Deacon, a neuroscientist who has been
working in anthropology for years, has a better hypothesis:
the human brain has the architecture of a chimpanzee brain
with an extensive symbol processing system built on top.
In his later philosophy, Wittgenstein showed the wide range
of "language games" that people play with their symbol systems.
The various logics that logicians construct and philosophers
and linguists study are different abstractions from the many
different kinds of language games that people play.
5. "A logic can only be a logic when expressed in a (formal)
language (see (9))."
A formally defined syntax certainly helps to clarify the
operations, but any argument stated in any formal logic can
be restated in an equally precise way in English and many
other natural languages. (I'll avoid making a commitment
about "all" languages, since some of them may need to add
vocabulary and possibly some syntax to support all logics.)
6. "A proposition is the mental act of assigning a property to
an entity or n-tuple of entities."
First of all, propositions are not acts, and they are
independent of the minds that conceive them. Furthermore,
propositions may relate continuous signs to continuous
referents that can't be analyzed as n-tuples.
Peirce noted that propositions can be made by pointing,
and they can also be expressed in images. For example,
a portrait with "George Washington" underneath states
"This is a likeness of George Washington."
8. "A logic is a formal system for deriving entailments (or:
defining inconsistencies)."
Deduction is only one way of using logic, and it's not
even the most important way. Induction and abduction are
prior to deduction because they're necessary to form the
hypotheses from which deduction proceeds. Furthermore,
hypotheses derived by induction and abduction can often
be useful without any further deduction. (If you think
you see a tiger about to pounce on you, don't waste time
in testing the hypothesis or deducing the consequences.)
10. "This discussion is limited to the logical constants ALL,
SOME, NOT, AND, OR."
That limitation and the assumptions about truth and
propositions (2), formality (5), and entailments (8)
drastically restrict what Seuren is willing to accept as
a "natural" logic. I believe that Seuren is "throwing out
the baby with the bathwater."
11. "A sentence of a NATURAL LANGUAGE L is transformationally
derived from the corresponding S of an underlying LOGICAL
or SEMANTIC LANGUAGE (LL)..."
That was a common assumption in the 1960s and '70s in
several different fields. In linguistics, it included both
the "generative semantics" movement, in which Seuren was a
participant, and the formal semantics movement, which was
started by Richard Montague and promoted by Hans Kamp and
Barbara Partee. It was also widely assumed in artificial
intelligence by people who hated logic, such as Roger Schank,
and by many people who used logic, such as me.
Today, many of those people are dead, and others have adopted
much broader views about language and logic. For the more
recent position by Hans Kamp, see
http://www.illc.uva.nl/lia/farewell_kamp.html
13. "Natural logical intuitions are a mixed lot... when separated
out into basic-natural and strict-natural they make for two
(or more) consistent systems."
I agree with the first sentence. But for the rest, Seuren
carefully selects which intuitions he considers natural.
I have serious doubts about his choices. See point 10.
14. "Every logic is definable in terms of a set theory. Standard
predicate logic is a direct reflex of standard set theory."
If you broaden the term 'set theory' to mean any way of talking
about collections and referring to their elements, the first
sentence is true but meaningless. The second sentence is false.
15. "Basic-natural set theory (BNST) analyses the cognitive concept
of PLURALITY."
Many linguists and logicians (including anyone who has tried to
teach conventional set theory to beginners) have observed that
the usual set theory does not have an obvious mapping to plurals,
as used in English and many other languages. For that reason,
many people have proposed versions of mereology as a better
foundation. But there are many more versions of mereology than
there are of set theory, and none of them have an obvious claim
to be natural. I have far less hope for Seuren's BNST.
16. "Natural human ONTOLOGY must be taken to include INTENSIONAL or
VIRTUAL ENTITIES, because humans refer to and quantify over virtual
entities (e.g. Greek gods) with the same ease and naturalness as
they do with regard to really existing (actual) entities (Seuren
2009, Ch. 2)."
I certainly agree with that point. But a better citation is
Ockham's _Summa Logicae_ (1323).
21. "Extensive data... show that two kinds of negation must be
distinguished in natural language: MINIMAL NEGATION to correct
failure to satisfy an update condition and metalinguistic,
discourse-correcting RADICAL NEGATION to correct failure to
satisfy a precondition."
Those are only two of the many, many ways that negative terms
are used in natural languages. It's another example of the way
that Seuren picks and chooses which "intuitions" he considers
to be "data".
As I said about point 11, I had a lot more sympathy with Seuren's
approach in the 1970s than I do today. In fact, I cited his books
from 1969 and 1974 in my 1984 book _Conceptual Structures_.
But even in that book, where I presented conceptual graphs as
a candidate for something one might call a "natural logic" or
a "discourse representation," I called Chapter 7 "The Limits
of Conceptualization." In that chapter and in many of my later
writings, I discussed the numerous problems and issues that any
claims about a "natural logic" must address. See, for example,
my paper on "The Challenge of Knowledge Soup":
http://www.jfsowa.com/pubs/challenge.pdf
I still believe that conceptual graphs are a useful representation
for many of the purposes that Seuren and others have claimed. But
in our current work at VivoMind, we use them in much more flexible
ways (of which formal deduction is just one). See, for example,
http://www.jfsowa.com/talks/paradigm.pdf
Two paradigms are better than one and
multiple paradigms are even better
The writings by Peirce and the later Wittgenstein had a strong
influence on my 1984 book, and their influence has grown even
stronger today. I don't believe that Seuren could have made
the assumptions above if he had done either of the following:
1. Spent some years working on natural language processing or
at least collaborating with people who did (as Kamp had done).
Alan Perlis said "A year spent in artificial intelligence
is enough to make one believe in God."
2. Read Peirce and Wittgenstein and taken their arguments
seriously.
As I said in my previous note, every version of logic is an
abstraction from the way reasoning is expressed in ordinary
language. As Wittgenstein pointed out, there are infinitely
many different "language games" that can be played with the
syntax and vocabulary of any natural language. I would say
that all of them are "natural" to a greater or lesser degree.
Furthermore, we have implemented computer systems that use
conceptual graphs to play many of those language games.
Seuren's assumptions about what is natural are too limited
to support the ways people actually use language.
PDM> could you interpret at a glance the transition from the
> square to the dodecadron (that would save me having to study
> the paper for the mo)
The square is sufficient to make the point. The dodecahedron
is an extension that incorporates more of Seuren's assumptions,
which are interesting, but dubious hypotheses.
John
-- Paola Di Maio ************************************************** Networked Research Lab, UK
***************************************************
_________________________________________________________________
Message Archives: http://ontolog.cim3.net/forum/ontolog-forum/
Config Subscr: http://ontolog.cim3.net/mailman/listinfo/ontolog-forum/
Unsubscribe: mailto:ontolog-forum-leave@xxxxxxxxxxxxxxxx
Shared Files: http://ontolog.cim3.net/file/
Community Wiki: http://ontolog.cim3.net/wiki/
To join: http://ontolog.cim3.net/cgi-bin/wiki.pl?WikiHomePage#nid1J
To Post: mailto:ontolog-forum@xxxxxxxxxxxxxxxx (01)
|