Tom, Leo
I disagree with you on several points. Of course it is sometimes as Leo
describes that programs blindly follow todays requirements, etc. But this is not
always the case. Provided one can stay within budget constraints, generalization
is often done and sometimes has great payoff. The General Dynamics F-16 is a
case of this. In my opinion generalization that adds a lot of extra cost, is
often spurious. Also within a program interoperability (not the same thing as
generalization) often plays a critical role, particularly when it is absent. I
can give lots of examples of this which have cost very large sums of money. As a
result there is now greater incentive in industry to address interoperability.
I have spent about 25 years in the aerospace trenches dealing with these
kinds of issues
Henson Graves
Sent: Thursday, October 15, 2015 2:28 PM
Subject: Re: [ontolog-forum] A Question About Mathematical
Logic
Dear
Leo,
You
wrote:
the
typical contractor problem (or one of those) is that you don’t generalize or
consider interoperability issues on any given budget/funding. You blindly follow
today’s requirements, provide a system that approximates those. Then you do it
again, and again, and again.
I
very, very, very strongly agree!
The
reason it is a problem is due to the way in which congress funds
developments. The lowest bid of sufficient quality is ALWAYS the
winner. They don't fund speculative projects because those projects will
be funded in future years. So if it is not part of the system requirements
that the system be interoperable with some future system, then the contractors
have no way to implement that unknown, unspecified, future system. If you
can't specify that future, you can't expect to plan cost effectively for
it.
But
that is the way business is done in all established large companies also, not
just in congress. It is bad investment practice to "anticipate" what has
only a small probability of being the actual system. We know that from
past examinations of the system corpses. So attempts to "anticipate"
usually cause waste and damage because there is no firm specification to design
to.
It’s
a way to keep getting funded, because everyone at some point needs your stuff.
So you create silo after silo after silo. Then at some point another program
comes up that focuses on interoperability, and then it pays for the vast
interoperability issues based on a hundred silos. And guess what, some of the
same companies that created the silos now get to correct their lack of
interoperability. Which is at that point, much more complex, and much more
costly, and typically fails.
You
are absolutely correct! Single step funding is the process which DoD uses,
partly under review by congressional committees, to manage the vast sums and
huge task lists required to complete a complex software system (with its
application ontology). That is the same process used by well established
businesses that are growing incrementally. Because history shows that it
works, it gets used again and again. History also shows that attempts to
anticipate future systems is essentially useless in most past project
outcomes.
Interoperability,
Si!
A
Priori Interoperability, No, Nada, Never!
Unless
... you can come up with a disruptive technology. My guess is that there
might be a way to transform the data dictionary and metadata into some
preconfigured abstractions of an industry vertical area, and use prewritten
interpreters for each domain method. That would likely be realistic in a
second project, but not in the first system development step.
That
is why, in an earlier email, I suggested writing domain DLLs that are common to
the vertical market. But even then you are going to have to do
customization for anything that deviates from that mystical vertical industry
standard in even one concept, or one concept's one method.
The
deeper you look into each vertical industry, the more uniqueness you find
in every company. Companies evolve into their niches. So one
approach might be to put ALL concepts known in a vertical into EVERY system to
support that vertical. Again, that adds complexity at the exponential
level for custom work. But it might reduce some of the labor of reaching
interoperability in future system development steps.
In
the long run, the best approach is to continue the current practice due to
budgeting and management constraints, and then to review several vertical uses
of the first system. From the database and displays, you can then identify
the concepts in the first system.
Develop
the DLLs next, adding whatever new concepts you can muster by reinterpreting the
first system concepts, relationships, instances, grouping, aggregating,
ordering, and all that good stuff needed by the vertical players.
So
if DoD used a similar approach, but tailored to DoD culture and best practices,
it would likely result in benefits on the cost of interoperability of the kinds
you described, Leo. But I don't see much that can be done during the first
system development step to pre-interoperate. The there isn't really there
yet.
Sincerely,
Rich
Cooper,
Rich
Cooper,
Chief
Technology Officer,
MetaSemantics
Corporation
MetaSemantics
AT EnglishLogicKernel DOT com
( 9
4 9 ) 5 2 5-5 7 1 2
http://www.EnglishLogicKernel.com
From:
ontolog-forum-bounces@xxxxxxxxxxxxxxxx
[mailto:ontolog-forum-bounces@xxxxxxxxxxxxxxxx] On Behalf Of Obrst, Leo
J. Sent: Thursday, October 15, 2015 11:30 AM To:
[ontolog-forum] ; 'Thomas Johnston' Subject: Re: [ontolog-forum] A
Question About Mathematical Logic
Sorry,
Rich, this is a method to perpetuate silos, not to address, at least
partially, interoperability issues with every project. In the DoD (and I worked
at Boeing at one time), the typical contractor problem (or one of those) is that
you don’t generalize or consider interoperability issues on any given
budget/funding. You blindly follow today’s requirements, provide a system that
approximates those. Then you do it again, and again, and again. It’s a way to
keep getting funded, because everyone at some point needs your stuff. So you
create silo after silo after silo. Then at some point another program comes up
that focuses on interoperability, and then it pays for the vast interoperability
issues based on a hundred silos. And guess what, some of the same companies that
created the silos now get to correct their lack of interoperability. Which is at
that point, much more complex, and much more costly, and typically fails.
Engineering
with blinders and halters is not good engineering.
Thanks,
Leo
From:
ontolog-forum-bounces@xxxxxxxxxxxxxxxx
[mailto:ontolog-forum-bounces@xxxxxxxxxxxxxxxx] On Behalf Of Rich
Cooper Sent: Thursday, October 15, 2015 1:08 PM To: 'Thomas
Johnston' <tmj44p@xxxxxxx>; '[ontolog-forum] '
<ontolog-forum@xxxxxxxxxxxxxxxx> Subject: Re: [ontolog-forum] A
Question About Mathematical Logic
Dear
Tom,
Your
emails are showing very, very small text fonts. So I copied an repasted in
larger font to make it more readable. You wrote:
But
if later on, someone wants to create a unified ontology of income-producing
instruments for a vertical industry group, then each company's ontology fragment
has to be integrated/bridged to the others.
The
financial issue is who is going to pay for the later
on
work. That is, by definition, a change in the requirements. It is
that change which I was speaking about in the earlier emails. I understand
and agree that situations like the one you described are common. But the
original development should not be burdened with the requirement, which
sacrifices costs, schedules, functionality and performance of the software
system. I don't believe in the practice of "paying
ahead"
by adding the extra cost, schedule, complexity, computing load, storage areas,
and representations needed to add the extra functions that just MIGHT be needed
in the future, but aren't needed at the first development.
I
have no argument with using philosophical concepts (even the Xdurants, which
nobody but philosophers care about), so long as they bring an immediate
benefit,
not a possible,
forecast, to be considered, future requirement.
If
you could come up with a scenario showing why it is useful in the FIRST system,
before the requirement actually does change, and justify it by that benefit
alone, not by the possible future benefit which may never arrive.
Can
you show better functionality, or better completeness, or some such
measure of effectiveness (MOE) on the FIRST system for adding that
stuff?
Sincerely,
Rich
Cooper,
Rich
Cooper,
Chief
Technology Officer,
MetaSemantics
Corporation
MetaSemantics
AT EnglishLogicKernel DOT com
( 9
4 9 ) 5 2 5-5 7 1 2
http://www.EnglishLogicKernel.com
From: Thomas Johnston [mailto:tmj44p@xxxxxxx] Sent:
Thursday, October 15, 2015 9:29 AM To: Rich Cooper; '[ontolog-forum]
' Subject: Re: [ontolog-forum] A Question About Mathematical
Logic
I don't
think I have misunderstood the engineers in this thread, and I haven't seen any
comments yet that persuade me I have.
Your
"Philosophy", if it's in reference to my comments, is formal ontology,
especially upper-level ontology. I do agree that lower-level ontology fragments
-- product hierarchies is an example I often use -- can stand alone, without any
"philosophical justification". But if later on, someone wants to create a
unified ontology of income-producing instruments for a vertical industry group,
then each company's ontology fragment has to be integrated/bridged to the
others. Suppose company X doesn't distinguish between products (e.g. tile for a
bathroom) and services (the installation of those tiles in a customer's home); X
has an ontology which includes ":installed bathroom flooring", but company Y, on
the other hand, has no such item in its inventory. For Y, floor tiling is a
product, and installation is a service that uses that
product.
The
"philosophical" question here is whether the mid-level ontology (for the
vertical industry group) should include "installed product" as an ontological
category. Whether or not it does, X and the other companies who use "installed
product" as a category, or Y and the other companies who do not, will have to do
a lot of database re-engineering in order to conform to the industry group
ontology. "Doing philosophy", in the sense of establishing ontologies, gets
right down to nitty-gritty software engineering work for the engineers who
thought that high-flown upper-level ontology work was irrlevant to the practical
work that engineers do.
Later on,
even upper-level ontologies can become relevant to such nitty-gritty work as
re-engineering databases. In scientific databases, it matters whether space and
time are represented as discrete or continuous. With respect to my own work, I
have suggested that distinguishing three temporal dimensions in databases
enables us to record and retrieve important information that the ISO-standard
two temporal dimensions cannot. And I would emphasize that introducing a third
temporal dimension was not just a matter of adjusting software to manage
temporal triples instead of temporal pairs. If that's all it were, then a
software engineer might think that every date/time piece of metadata for the
rows of a database table would constitute a new temporal "dimension"; and that
outlook has lighted many fools the way to dusty software
death.
Instead, a
third temporal dimension is introduced based on the "philosophical" distinction
between (i) inscriptions of declarative sentences (rows in tables), (ii) the
statement that multiple copies of the same row are inscriptions of; (iii) the
propositions that synonymous statements are expressions of; and (iv) the
propositional attitudes that users of databases express when they update
databases, and presuppose when they query those databases. It is also based on
an extension of Aristotle's basic ontology, an extension which I describe in
Chapter 5 of my oft-alluded-to book.
This is
doing philosophy, in anyone's book. It is what led me to recognize the existence
of a new ontological category -- the temporal dimension I called "speech-act
time" in my book. Ontology engineers who plug in lexical items for concepts in
non-controversial fragments of ontologies, don't have to do ontology. In that, I
agree with you. But once those engineers are tasked with extending their
constructs beyond the non-controversial scope of those constructs, they get in
trouble (cf my "customer" example, also my "installed product" and third
temporal dimension discussed in this comment). They get in trouble because they
are then confronted with the need to do ontology; they enter an arena in which
they will be forced to "do philosophy" -- which is something that they feel in
their guts (and have often expressed in this forum) is irrelevant to the "REAL"
work that engineers do.
I don't
expect to convince you. But I do believe it's worth trying to say, as clearly as
I can, what my understanding of the issue of doing formal ontology vs. doing
ontology engineering is. My understanding is that both are important, that, to
paraphrase Kant, "ontology without engineering is empty; engineering without
ontology is blind".
I have seen
several remarks, by the engineers among us, about ontology and
semantics being irrelevant to the work they do, being irrelevant,
as you put it, to "real engineering problems". But I have also seen the
confusion engineers create when they work with anything other than
uncontroversial ontology fragments, e.g. a company's product hierarchy.
No!
You're missing the point about engineering. Philosophical
justifications for ontologies is what I, perhaps among others, disagree
with. But the need for an ontology within a complex software
architecture, and therefore the need for clear precise semantics for
interpreting that ontology's components, in all situations, is a primary
engineering concern.
It is only
the philosophy part, the attempt to link application ontologies to some
overarching totality of existential ontology insisted upon from that
philosophical perspective that perturbs this engineer, likely others. Its
adding unnecessary complexity to the architecture of the software, which
should be minimized, not expanded.
Every
addition of one more component to an ontology drives its complexity up in an
exponential curve. Not a good thing for developing software
especially. So adding even more components having only philosophical
justification and not specifically application justification is the
wrong direction, IMHO.
Chief
Technology Officer,
MetaSemantics
Corporation
MetaSemantics
AT EnglishLogicKernel DOT com
From: Thomas
Johnston [mailto:tmj44p@xxxxxxx]
Sent: Tuesday, October 13, 2015 6:05 PM To: Rich Cooper;
'[ontolog-forum] ' Subject: Re: [ontolog-forum] A Question About
Mathematical Logic
Like an
earlier comment, yours emphasizes, I believe, the need to discuss (i) the
difference between formal ontology and ontology engineering (which is roughly
the difference between theory and practice), and (ii) the problems that arise
when ontology engineers finding themselves having to do ontology, rather than
having to just plug uncontroversial mini-ontologies into some well-defined
framework (like Protege) or into a framework/template toolkit like OWL/RDF. I
intend to do this in a new thread, and soon.
I have seen
several remarks, by the engineers among us, about ontology and semantics being
irrelevant to the work they do, being irrelevant, as you put it, to "real
engineering problems". But I have also seen the confusion engineers create when
they work with anything other than uncontroversial ontology fragments, e.g. a
company's product hierarchy.
As an
ontologist, and a person somewhat familiar with systems of logic, I nonetheless
appreciate the importance of getting ontologies into frameworks. That, in my
opinion, is what puts the semantics in the Semantic Web -- it gives automated
systems, doing cross-database queries, the ability to understand cross-database
semantics. (Pat Hayes to correct me, please, if I'm off course
here.)
An example I
have come across in every one of two dozen enterprises I have worked for, is the
question: "What is a customer?", where that question, more fully, means "What
does your enterprise take a customer of yours to be?" I have never found subject
matter experts who have been able to answer that question, without a good deal
of help from me. And the help I provide is help in doing ontology clarification
work, not help in plugging lexical items representing ontological categories
into an ontology tool. Moreover, I have never found two enterprises whose
experts defined "customer" in exactly the same
way.
From which
it follows that a cross-database query that assumes that two tables named
"Customer Table", in two different enterprise's databases, are both about
customers, is almost certain to be mistaken. Both tables may be about fruit, but
there is certain to be an apples and oranges issue there.
A formal
ontology which includes customers, on the other hand, might be able to
distinguish apples from oranges if it could access an ontology framework about
customers. Given that the concepts have been correctly and extensively-enough
clarified, here is where the ontology engineer proves his worth.
But to
define the category Customer clearly enough, it isn't engineering work that
needs to be done. It's the far more difficult (in my opinion) ontology
clarification work that needs to be done. (I expand on this example in the
section "On Using Ontologies", pp. 73-74 in my book Bitemporal Data: Theory and
Practice. I think I also elaborated on it a few weeks or months ago, here at
Ontolog.)
So I think
that engineers who suggest that clarifying ontological categories is irrelevant
to their work as ontology engineers, are mistaken. Such work seems mistaken to
them, I think, because most of the ontologies they put into their well-defined
frameworks are relatively trivial, i.e. are ontologies that subject matter
experts have no trouble agreeing on. The lower-level the ontologies we engineer,
the more that will tend to be the case.
But ascend
into mid-level or upper-level ontologies, and ontology engineers get lost, and
don't know how to find a clear path through the forest whose trees are those
categories. And so instead of admitting "We're lost", they say instead "We
strayed into a swamp that has nothing to do with the real engineering work we do
-- which turns out to be the relatively straightforward work of plugging labels
for uncontroversial ontological categories, and taxonomies thereof, into Protege
or its like".
I say, on
the contrary, that conceptual clarification work in mid- and upper-level
ontologies have everything to do with ontology engineering, and are where the
really difficult work of that engineering is done. An analogy: machine-tooling
parts is the hard work of manufacturing; assembling those parts is the easy
work.
And my
apologies to Leo, Pat and other whose comments on my question I have not yet
responded to. I will, and soon. And I thank them and all other respondents for
helping me think through the question I
raised.
Although
the approach you are suggesting might entertain some philosophical questions,
and therefore be entertaining to philosophers, it has little or no relevance to
real engineering problems, which almost never are applied to the actual universe
of every possible entity - i.e. infinite supplies.
In
engineering applications, Ex(...) would normally apply only to finite sized, or
traversably infinite sized, problems. The importance of scope in
engineering, i.e., where you draw the lines around what is a system, which
contains all the entities, enumerators of variables, constants and functions in
real problems.
Even
unbounded engineering problems have limits to the possible types that can be
used, though mechanisms like stacks, or even Turing machines with infinite
square supplies, attempt to approximate boundless sizes.
So I
suggest your title should be A Question About Mathematical Logic, since
engineers who consider themselves logic designers would find the ideas
impractical, though linguists might be more interested.
Chief
Technology Officer,
MetaSemantics
Corporation
MetaSemantics
AT EnglishLogicKernel DOT com
Suppose
someone else asserts, instead, that "No dogs are renates". Certainly, to do
that, that person must believe that there are such things as dogs and, in
addition, believe that none of them are renates (a false belief, of
course).
On Tuesday,
October 13, 2015 11:57 AM, Thomas Johnston <tmj44p@xxxxxxx> wrote:
My
intuitions tell me that anyone who asserts "All dogs are renates" believes that
there are dogs (i.e. is ontologically committed to the existence of dogs) just
as much as someone who asserts "Some dogs are friendly".
Suppose
someone else asserts, instead, that "No dogs are renates". Certainly, to do
that, that person must believe that there are such things as dogs and, in
addition, believe that some of them are not renates (a false belief, of course).
Now for
"Some dogs are friendly", and also "Some dogs are not friendly". In both cases,
we all seem to agree, someone making those assertions believes that there are
dogs.
Now I'm
quite happy about all this. If I make a Gricean-rule serious assertion by using
either the "All" quantification or the "Some" quantification, I'm talking about
whatever is the subject term in those quantifications – dogs in this case. I'm
particularly happy that negation, as it appears in the deMorgan's translations
between "All" statements and "Some" statements, doesn't claim that a pair of
statements are semantically equivalent, in which one of the pair expresses a
belief that dogs exist but the other does not.
But in the
standard interpretation of predicate logic, that is the interpretation. In the
standard interpretation, negating a statement creates or removes the _expression_
of a belief that something exists. My beliefs in what exist can't be changed by
the use of the negation operator. Apparently, John's beliefs can, and so too for
everyone else who feels comfortable with predicate logic as a formalization of
commonsense reasoning, and with the interpretation of one of its operators as
"There exists ....".
I usually
don't like getting into tit for tats. Those kinds of discussions always are
about trees, and take attention away from the forest. But I'll make exceptions
when I think it's worth taking that risk (as I did in my response to Ed last
night).
From John
Sowa's Oct 12th
response:
TJ > why, in
the formalization of predicate logic, was it decided > that
"Some X" would carry ontological commitment
Nobody made
that decision. It's a fact of perception. Every observation
can always be described with just two operators: existential
quantifier and conjunction. No other operators can be observed.
They can only be inferred.
(1) If all
ontological commitments have to be based on direct observation, then we're right
back to the Vienna Circle and A. J. Ayer.
(2) And what
is it that we directly observe? A dog in front of me? Dogs, as Quine once
pointed out, are ontological posits on a par with the Greek gods, or with
disease-causing demons. (I am aware that this point, in particular, will likely
serve to reinforce the belief, on the part of many engineering types in this
forum, that philosophy has nothing to do with ontology engineering. That's
something I want to discuss in a "contextualizing discussion" I want to have
before I pester the members of this forum with questions and hypotheses about
cognitive/diachronic semantics. What does talk like that have to do with
building real-world ontologies in ontology tools, in OWL/RDF – ontologies that
actually do something useful in the world?
(3) I
wouldn't talk about some dogs unless I believed that some dogs exist. And if
some dogs exist, then all dogs do, too. Either there are dogs, or there aren't.
If there are, then I can talk about some of them, or about all of them. If there
aren't, then unless I am explicitly talking about non-existent things, I can't
talk about some of them nor can I talk about all of them, for the simple reason
that none of them exist. To repeat myself: if any of them exist, then all of
them do.
(4) And I
am, of course, completely aware that trained logicians since Frege have been
using predicate logic, and that, at least since deMorgan, have been importing to
negation the power to create and remove ontological commitment.
(5) Here's a
quote from Paul Vincent Spade (very important guy in
medieval logic and semantics):
"This
doctrine of “existential import” has taken a lot of silly abuse in the twentieth
century. As you may know, the modern reading of universal affirmatives construes
them as quantified material conditionals. Thus ‘Every S is P’ becomes (x)(Sx
⊃ Px), and is true, not false, if there are
no S’s. Hence (x)(Sx ⊃ Px) does not imply (∃x)(Sx). And that is somehow supposed to
show the failure of existential import. But it doesn’t show
anything of the sort .... "
So Spade
approaches this as the issue of the existential import of universally quantified
statements. He points out that, from Ux(Dx --> Rx), we cannot infer Ex(Dx
& Rx). The rest of the passage attempts to explain why. I still either don't
understand his argument, or I'm not convinced by it. Why should "All dogs are
renates" not be expressed as Ux(Dx & Rx)?
From John's
reply, I think he would say that it's because we can only observe particular
things; we can't observe all things. But in the preceding points, I've tried to
say why I don't find that convincing.
(6) Simply
the fact that decades of logicians have not raised the concerns I have raised
strongly suggests that I am mistaken, and need to think more clearly about logic
and ontological commitment. But there is something that might make one hesitate
to jump right to that conclusion. It's Kripke's position on analytic a
posteriori statements (which I have difficulty distinguishing from Kant's
synthetic a priori statements, actually -- providing we assume that the
metaphors of "analytic" as finding that one thing is "contained in" another
thing, and of "synthetic" as bringing together two things first experienced as
distinct, are just metaphors, and don't work as solid explanations).
All analytic
statements are "All" statements, not "Some" statements. Kripke suggests that the
statement "Water is H2O" is analytic but a posteriori. In general, that "natural
kind" statements are all of this sort. Well, a posteriori statements are ones
verified by experience, and so that would take care of John's Peircean point
that only "Some" statements are grounded in what we experience.
I don't know
how solid this line of thought is. But if there is something to it, that might
suggest that if we accept Kripke's whole referential semantics / rigid
designator / natural kinds ideas (cf. Putnam's twin earth thought experiment
also), then perhaps we should rethink the traditional metalogical interpretation
of "All dogs are renates" as Ux(Dx --> Rx), and consider, instead, Ux(Dx
& Rx).
Well, two
summing-up points. The first is that Paul Vincent Spade thinks that my position
is "silly", and John Sowa thinks that it's at least wrong. The second is that
such discussions do indeed take us beyond the concerns of ontology engineers,
who just want to get on with building working ontologies.
As I said
above, I will address those concerns of ontology engineers before I begin
discussing cognitive semantics in this Ontolog (Ontology + Logic) forum.
Tom, Ed,
Leo, Paul, Henson,
TJ > why, in the formalization of predicate
logic, was it decided > that "Some X" would carry ontological
commitment
Nobody made that decision. It's a fact of
perception. Every observation can always be described with just two
operators: existential quantifier and conjunction. No other operators
can be observed. They can only be inferred.
EJB > I was taught
formal logic as a mathematical discipline, not > a philosophical
discipline. I do not believe that mathematics > has any interest in
ontological commitment.
That's true. And most of the people who
developed formal logic in the 20th c were mathematicians. They didn't
worry about the source or reliability of the starting
axioms.
Leo > most ontologists of the realist persuasion will argue
that there > are no negated/negative ontological things.
Whatever
their persuasion, nobody can observe a negation. It's always an
inference or an assumption.
PT > on the inadequacy of mathematical
logic for reasoning about > the real world, see Veatch, "Intentional
Logic: a logic based on > philosophical realism".
Many different
logics can be and have been formalized for various purposes. They may
have different ontological commitments built in, but the distinction of what
is observed or inferred is critical.
HG > I keep wondering if this
forum has anything useful to offer the > science and engineering
community.
C. S. Peirce was deeply involved in experimental physics
and engineering. He was also employed as an associate editor of
the _Century Dictionary_, for which he wrote, revised, or edited
over 16,000 definitions. My comments below are based on CSP's
writings:
1. Any sensory perception is evidence that something
exists; a simultaneous perception of something A and
something B is evidence for (Ex)(Ey)(A(x) &
B(y)).
2. Evidence for other operators must *always* be an
inference:
(a) Failure to observe P(x) does not mean
there is no P.
Example:
"There is no hippopotamus in this
room" can only be inferred iff you
have failed to observe a hippo and
know that it is big enough that you
would certainly have noticed one
if it were present.
(b) (p or q) cannot be directly
observed. But you might
infer that a particular
observation (e.g. "the room is
lighted") could be the result of
two or more sources.
(c) (p implies q) cannot be
observed, as Hume discussed at length.
(d) a universal
quantifier can never be observed. No
matter how many examples of P(x)
you see, you can never know that
you've seen them all (unless you have other
information that guarantees you
have seen them all).
TJ > But now notice something: negation
creates and removes ontological > commitment. And this seems really
strange. Why should negation do this?
The commitment is derived from the
same background knowledge that enabled you to assert (or prevented you from
asserting) the negation.
> I'd also like to know if there are formal
logics which do not > impute this extravagant power of ontological
commitment / > de-commitment to the negation operator in predicate
logics.
Most formal logicians don't think about these issues -- for
the simple reason that most of them are mathematicians. They
don't think about observation and evidence.
CSP realized the
problematical issues with negation, but he also knew that he needed to assume
at least one additional operator. And negation was the simplest of the
lot. Those are the three he assumed for his existential graphs.
(But he later added metalanguage, modality, and three values -- T, F, and
Unknown.)
John
PS: The example "There is no hippopotamus in
this room" came from a remark by Bertrand Russell that he couldn't convince
Wittgenstein that there was no hippopotamus in the room. Russell didn't
go into any detail, but I suspect that Ludwig W. was trying to explain the
point that a negation cannot be observed.
_________________________________________________________________ Message
Archives: http://ontolog.cim3.net/forum/ontolog-forum/ Config Subscr:
http://ontolog.cim3.net/mailman/listinfo/ontolog-forum/ Unsubscribe:
mailto:ontolog-forum-leave@xxxxxxxxxxxxxxxx Shared Files:
http://ontolog.cim3.net/file/ Community Wiki: http://ontolog.cim3.net/wiki/
To join:
http://ontolog.cim3.net/cgi-bin/wiki.pl?WikiHomePage#nid1J
|
_________________________________________________________________
Message Archives: http://ontolog.cim3.net/forum/ontolog-forum/
Config Subscr: http://ontolog.cim3.net/mailman/listinfo/ontolog-forum/
Unsubscribe: mailto:ontolog-forum-leave@xxxxxxxxxxxxxxxx
Shared Files: http://ontolog.cim3.net/file/
Community Wiki: http://ontolog.cim3.net/wiki/
To join: http://ontolog.cim3.net/cgi-bin/wiki.pl?WikiHomePage#nid1J (01)
|